Critique of Edwards’ View of the Will

In this section I will be critiquing Edwards' views on the will and freedom. I won't be presenting the alternative view, LFW, nor will I attempt to demonstrate the logical outcomes of Edwards view (i.e. God is the author of sin, God's offer is insincere…). Instead I will just be looking at the internal consistency of Edwards' view. I really think that the more people understand Edwards, the less they will agree with him.

Brief Outline of Edwards' view of Freedom

Except where specifically cited, all quotes taken from Part 1.
The Will

Edwards defines the will as "that by which the mind chooses any thing" and describes it as "for in every act of will whatsoever, the mind chooses one thing rather than another; it chooses something rather than the contrary or rather than the want or non-existence of that thing."

What Determines the Will?

Edwards goes on to ask the question "What determines the will?" Edwards responds that the will is determined by "the strongest motive" and states that "the will always is, as the greatest apparent good is" and that "the will follows the last dictate of understanding". To Edwards, the understanding perceives the alternatives, weighs them, projects the consequences of acting on them, finds one most agreeable and dictates which is best. Then the will follows suit.

Why does the understanding dictate this, not that option is best? The understanding operates deterministically; given certain inputs, you get certain outputs. For Edwards the mix of 1) a man's state of mind, 2) the mind's view of the objects and 3) the perceived qualities of objects under consideration cause the understanding to dictate to the will that an option is best. The state of mind is a product of a person's nature and experiences. The mind's view is a question of how certain a person is of an outcome and how clearly he understands the object. Given a person's present state of mind and the mind's view of the object, the object "causes it to appear most agreeable". So under the right circumstances, if you look at an ice cream cone, it will cause your understanding to declare it best, which causes your will to choose it, which causes your body to eat it.

Necessity and Freedom

Edwards carefully classifies freedom and necessity into two buckets: common necessity and philosophical necessity. People talk about "common necessity" in day to day discussions; "philosophical necessity" is used in the Calvinism/Arminianism controversy. For Edwards, something is necessary, in the common sense, if the opposition to hinder it is insufficient. He defines philosophical necessity as the certainty of the thing itself. Philosophical necessity may or may not have something opposing it, but common necessity always supposes insufficient opposition. This is a bit abstract. An example of philosophical necessity is God's existence. No one's opposing God's existence, but it must be. An example of common necessity would be: I couldn't stop the running back from getting a touchdown.

Edwards defines freedom, in the common meaning, as "the power anyone has to do as he pleases". This type of freedom is opposed to compulsion (i.e. someone's got a knife to your throat) and inability (i.e. you wish to fly, but can't). Edwards denies there is such a thing as freedom, in the philosophical sense - everything is necessary in that sense.

Compatibilism

For Edwards, common necessity is incompatible with common freedom and philosophical necessity is incompatible with philosophical freedom (there is no such thing as philosophical freedom). Supposing that something is necessary and free, in the same sense, is a contradiction.

But Edwards does state that philosophical necessity is compatible with common freedom. Since Edwards established two alternative definitions for necessity, common and philosophical, something can be necessary in one sense and not necessary in another without contradiction. An example that Edwards gives is a drunk whose nature necessitates (in the philosophical sense) that he drink, but since no one is preventing his executing his choice to drink, he's free (in the common sense).


Freedom of the Will


Does Edwards believe in freewill? The answer isn't as clean cut as you might think, given the title of his book: "the Freedom of the Will". But what you have to realize is this title is abridged from the one Edwards gave: "A Careful and Strict Enquiry into the Modern Prevailing Notions of that Freedom of the Will, Which Is Supposed to be Essential to Moral Agency, Vertue and Vice, Reward and Punishment, Praise and Blame". Approximately, 85% of the book is dedicated to critiquing libertarian freewill, which Edwards admits is a modern prevailing notion, but denies is either true or essential for moral agency. So perhaps the abridged title misleads people into thinking Edwards believes in freewill.


In fact, Edwards distinguishes between freedom of persons and freedom of the will and claims "to talk of liberty, or the contrary, as belonging to the very will itself, is not to speak good sense; if we judge of sense, and nonsense, by the original and proper signification of the word". (Part I.V) A close reading of Edwards reveals that when he speaks of liberty, he isn't talking about an ability of the will, but rather he's typically speaking of the ability of the person to physically execute what they choose. For Edwards, the adjective free describes the person, not the will.


Edwards doesn't use the term freewill to describe his view throughout his book, but he does use the term "free choice" approvingly once. (Part II.V) So perhaps he does believe in freewill? But in this section Dr. Whitby (an Arminian) cited several church fathers claiming we have freewill. Edwards responds by saying the fathers' position is the same as the Calvinist one and quotes back the fathers' words in an approving way saying: "The soul acting by its own choice, men doing good or evil according to their own free choice, their being in that exercise which proceeds from their own free choice, having it in their choice to turn to good or evil, and doing what they will." But Edwards goes on to say "if men exercise this liberty in the acts of the will themselves [then the term "free choice" is reducible to an absurdity]. [brackets my summary of what Edwards said] But if freedom doesn't apply to choice, why use the term free choice? Edwards explains what he means by free choice by saying: "if any say [that liberty consists in the acts of the will themselves], one of these two things must be meant, either, 1. That a man has power to will, as he does will; because what he wills, he wills; and therefore power to will what he has power to will...[or 2 an absurd option]." So for Edwards' free choice either means a person wills what he wills, or it's absurd. But this sense is a very rare one through Edwards' book, and what he commonly means by freedom is a person's ability to do what they have chosen.

My thoughts on Edwards' Views

Inconsistency Related to Choice and Alternatives


Edwards' definition of choice does involve alternatives, but there's a problem. The understanding, which precedes and determines the choice, does all the heavy lifting when it comes to the alternatives. The understanding perceives the alternatives, weighs them, projects the consequences of acting on them, finds one most agreeable and dictates which is best. So what exactly does the will have to do with the alternative not acted upon? The understanding already eliminated the alternatives before the will comes into the picture. Edwards' view of the will is so far from the will being able to choose between the alternatives that it actually seems as if he's inconsistent to say choice has anything to do with alternatives at all.

Two Different Meanings for Necessity
Edwards splits two different senses for necessity ("common necessity" with insufficient opposition and "philosophical necessity" without opposition). I disagree these are two alternative senses- it's one sense in two different contexts. Why this matters will be much more apparent when we get into Edwards arguments against libertarian freewill.

Edwards on Compatibilism

I will just point out that Edwards has to mix "common freedom" and "philosophical necessity" to get compatibilism to work and that this sense of compatibilism seem different that the one advocated by Calvinists today.

The Freedom of the Will vs. Freedom of the Body

Edwards' avocation of "common freedom" is about freedom of the body to execute choices. Although this sense of freedom is intuitive and compatible with "philosophical necessity", it's just not relevant to discussions about freewill. Interestingly, Edwards admits that this sense of freedom isn't the one debated between Calvinists and Arminians and is not what he's talking about when he says man is unable to obey God, grace is irresistible or God's commands apply directly to the will, not the body. But he still pushes this sense of freedom into the discussion, creating confusion.

As for the other sense of freedom of choice Edwards uses (i.e. a person wills what he wills), first off, it's tautological, second it's not what people generally mean by freewill, third, it's not a freedom regarding future possibilities, but rather present actualities, fourth, it's not a freedom of the will from something (i.e. necessity) or to something (i.e. to choose either alternative). So for these reasons I would say this sense of free choice isn't relevant to the Calvinists/Arminian debate and I am glad Edwards only used it once.

So in short, Edwards doesn't use the term freedom in any sense relevant to discussions of freewill, except to deny it. I personally would find Calvinists far more consistent if they would just go ahead and deny freewill.

Comments

Anonymous said…
Great to see you taking on Edwards here. Many calvinists like to go to Owen's arguments for limited atonement (which you have already wiped out in your previous series on Owen's book and arguments). For free will they like to appeal to Edwards' book on the will so it's great that you are taking that on now. After dispensing with Edwards' feeble arguments, where will the calvinists be able to turn? :-) You will have eliminated their crutches, they won't have much to lean on after that! What you are doing will also provide great ammunition for other noncalvinists who have to hear the same Owenesque and Edwardsian arguments. Great work, keep up the good work.

Robert
Anonymous said…
I don't understand Edward's position even after reading your post, because IMO his position is quite different from what the Bible teaches on this subject.

Dan, maybe you can explain this to me: in Edward's arguments against free will as he defines it, did Edward also deny that God has free will as well? If so, how did Edwards demonstrate that God who has no free will can still be considered sovereign? And if not, how did Edwards differentiate the will of God and the will of angels and humans?
Godismyjudge said…
Dear Robert,

Yep, Edwards is their go to guy on the will, although, from what I can tell what Edwards taught is a little different than modern Calvinism.

God be with you,
Dan
Godismyjudge said…
Dear Truehope,

Edwards view is a bit complex. The best analogy for his view on freedom comes from a political issue of his day - slavery. Edwards thought we are free in the sense that someone who isn't a slave is free. This view of freedom is accurate, but insufficient to say the will is free.


Good question on His view of God. Edwards said God doesn't have freewill. For Edwards, freewill is illogical, so therefore God couldn't have it. Further, Edwards argued that we only think it's impious to say God doesn't have freewill, because we think freewill is a good thing, but it's not. Edwards explains God's sovereignty, in that God determines everything [even though He couldn't have determined it to be otherwise]. I think this view has big problems.

Thanks for asking.

God be with you,
Dan
Rev. said…
You're not going to believe this, but I disagree with you. ;)

Edwards sounds very, very similar to Augustine on this point. I believe that both are correct in asserting "free will" and distinguishing it from "liberty." I also think it is important to distinguish this form of "free will" from the monstrosity of "human autonomy" that prevails within the contemporary evangelical context.

Where will "Calvinists" be able to turn if not to Owen or Edwards? We'll turn where we always have, to the Scriptures! ;)
Rev. said…
Also, as to Edwards, I'm not sure what you are saying in relation to his understanding of God's will. God always has "free will" in the sense that "Our God is in the heavens, He does whatever He pleases." However, He never does anything contrary to His ultimate desires or His nature. For example, God cannot lie.
Godismyjudge said…
Dear James,

I believe that both are correct in asserting "free will" and distinguishing it from "liberty."

A close reading of Edwards’ book reveals he doesn’t use the term freewill…except to argue against it. I would be interested if you could produce a counter example, but based on my research, I feel fairly comfortable saying Edwards didn’t believe in free will.

Rather, he believed in the freedom of the body to execute the will’s command. If your body can overpower your opposition, you are free. If not, you not free. But freedom (for Edwards) always modifies “you” and never your “will”. Your will isn’t free, your body is.

I need to research Augustine more.

Where will "Calvinists" be able to turn if not to Owen or Edwards? We'll turn where we always have, to the Scriptures!

No question about that! But here’s where I am going with this…

The three common views are: 1) LFW 2) Compatiblism and 3) Hard Determinism. #3 isn’t an option for Christians, because the bible says we have wills and make choices. So for us it’s down to 2 options. So if compatiblism is incoherent, then LFW is the last man standing and therefore the biblical option.

That’s why I am going through Edwards, because he is usually spoken of as the strongest Calvinist on this point. I actually don’t think he’s the strongest Calvinist on this point. I think Francis Turretin is, and his explanation is quite different than Edwards. But Edwards is cited more often than Turretin.

God be with you,
Dan
Rev. said…
Dan:
You may be right on the point about Turretin. I need to begin reading him more....

I concede that Edwards speaks of desire, etc., as the center of the will, and thereby argues about how the will is bound by those desires (not merely neutral). However (and I'm probably reading this through my Augustinian lens), I don't think this necessarily negates what would be defined as "free will."

Sometimes we just have to work through the terms we've become so accustomed to, don't we?

Brother, I appreciate your spirit and am glad we can peacefully chat about these matters.
Godismyjudge said…
Dear James,

I concede that Edwards speaks of desire, etc., as the center of the will, and thereby argues about how the will is bound by those desires (not merely neutral).

This is very interesting. You’re the third Calvinist I’ve seen make this claim about Edwards (i.e. the will is bound by desires). R. C. Sproul makes this claim in Chosen by God (p 53 & 54) and Theojunkie (see the link to his blog) made this claim as well… This claim doesn’t seem to be based on Edwards’ book on the freedom of the will. Edwards’ model seems to be: reason > choice not desire > choice. For Edwards, the will is bound by motive, which is a function of reason.


God be with you,
Dan
Rev. said…
Guess I'll be picking up Edwards this evening... :)
Rev. said…
Or even late afternoon. ;)

Looking back at Edwards' discussion of the nature of the will, I still believe he affirms that what I am calling "desire," he would say is "preference." He argues, in fact, that no volition exists without preference (I.I). Edwards writes that the will "always follows the last dictate of the understanding" (perception, not merely reason or judgment) (I.II). Thus, an intellectual grasp of a situation is tied to one's preference.

Using layman's terms - let's say a thief breaks into my home tonight and aims a shotgun at my head, telling me he wants all my cash, credit cards, jewels, etc. Do I have a desire to give him my possessions? Not exactly, but I do have a desire to live. Grasping the situation intellectually, my preference - greater preference / desire (what Edwards says is "most agreeable" - is to live, so I hand over my possessions.

I believe this is the essence of Edwards' argument.

The terms I'm employing, namely "liberty" and "free will," I put in quotes because of some of the differences in the terms which are employed by Edwards and Augustine (though, again, I believe they are arguing the same thing essentially). Edwards, for example, speaks of "Liberty" in the context of his day - what we might call "individual autonomy" in our context.

Just an extra note - I've been forced to consider Edwards' use of the term "Arminian" because of his context. This came about when I was working on my dissertation and I discussed the Edwards section with Iain Murray. Murray noted that the "Arminianism" faced (and detested) by Edwards was a much more Deistic, non-supernatural form of belief than what is actually held by the likes of Arminius, Wesley, etc.
Godismyjudge said…
Dear James,

Looking back at Edwards' discussion of the nature of the will, I still believe he affirms that what I am calling "desire," he would say is "preference." He argues, in fact, that no volition exists without preference (I.I). Edwards writes that the will "always follows the last dictate of the understanding" (perception, not merely reason or judgment) (I.II). Thus, an intellectual grasp of a situation is tied to one's preference.

This is close to the way I understand Edwards but not quite right. Let’s see… regarding preference…

Preference is synonymous with choice. It’s not that preference causes choice, but rather preference is choice. Choice (or preference) is the act of the will, and it follows the last dictate of the understanding. So again, it’s not preference > choice, but rather understanding > choice (where preference = choice).


Why does this matter? Let’s look at Edwards’ description of freedom and compare it to RC Sproul’s characterization of Edwards.

Edwards said: Freedom is the power, opportunity, or advantage, that any one has, to do as he pleases.(1.5)

Sproul characterizes Edwards as: “the ability to choose what we want” – Chosen by God, p 54

Edwards is saying: choose > do, Sproul is saying desire > choose. Edwards is talking about an ability to execute what we choose, Sproul is talking about an ability to choose. Edwards is talking about a freedom of the body, Sproul is talking about a freedom of the will.

That's a good point about the way Edwards is defining Arminian. I understand one of his "Arminian" opponents, Dr. Whitby, had some problems with Arianism.

God be with you,
Dan
Anonymous said…
James wrote:

“Using layman's terms - let's say a thief breaks into my home tonight and aims a shotgun at my head, telling me he wants all my cash, credit cards, jewels, etc. Do I have a desire to give him my possessions? Not exactly, but I do have a desire to live. Grasping the situation intellectually, my preference - greater preference / desire (what Edwards says is "most agreeable" - is to live, so I hand over my possessions.”

So you are confronted with a situation as described. You are also confronted with a choice that involves multiple accessible alternatives including: give up the possessions to not be killed; believe he is “bluffing” and refuse to give over the possessions; if you are skilled in martial arts and see an opportunity to disarm him refuse to give over the possessions and make an attempt to disarm him; if you are suicidal push him to kill you by taunting him, etc. etc. One of these possibilities will be actualized by you, will be your choice and will actualize a particular possibility while excluding other possibilities.

In other words, you face a choice, you have a choice and will then make a choice.

I believe that when we make choices we do so in line with our “importances” (my term for the fact we do things in line with what we consider important; e.g. if you want to live that is an importance that you may act upon and so choose to give up the possessions, or you may believe it important to disarm such a person because you have years of special training and do not want them to get away with a crime, etc. etc.). Now our importances do not necessitate or cause our actions, but when we choose to act we choose to act in line with them.
So in James’ example, if you **have** a choice you have multiple alternatives accessible to you, which you can actualize. And whichever possibility you choose to actualize, YOU will be the cause, YOU will be the factor that determines which possibility will be actualized.

Edwards said we did what we did because of our nature. But our “nature” never makes a choice, WE DO. Edwards said we act from our strongest desire. But WE DETERMINE which desire will be strongest. What makes one desire “stronger” than another? We do. When there are competing desires attached to different courses of action, as in this example, what factor makes some desires weaker and some stronger and one the strongest? I would say the person himself, determines which is the weakest, which is the strongest. No matter what he ends up choosing, his choice will be in line with his importances. And we choose what will be most important to us in a particular situation. So WE are the determining factor, the cause of our own intentional actions. And it is because WE are the source of the action, the factor that caused one possibility to be actualized rather than another, that WE can be held responsible for our actions.

Where Edwards really missed the boat is that his system of theology, which involves the claim that God predetermines every even that occurs, precludes us from ever having a choice. And yet he talks about having preferences and choices. If Edwards’s system is true then we never face a choice where we could actualize different possibilities in the same situation (we never have what some have called “contra-causal” freedom, or more simply, we never ever have a choice, we can never do otherwise than we were predetermined to do). So Edwards if he is consistent with his system, cannot speak about **having** a choice, about why one possibility is actualized by a choice and not another. Returning to James' example, if it is predetermined that I do not give my possessions to the intruder and die for it, then it was impossible for me to actualize the possibility of giving him my possessions in order to live (to do that I would be doing something other than what God had predetermined what I would do, which if exhaustive predeterminism is true, would be impossible). But if I can only make the choice of not giving up my possessions and dying for it, then I never had a choice. Edwards’ system cannot allow for us ever having choices, so in terms of explaining why we do make the choices we do when we have choices is useless.

Edwards has to borrow the concept of having a choice from the noncalvinist, to speak about having choices because his own system eliminates the possibility of us ever having choices. It should again be noted that situations as described by James involving us **having** choices, cannot exist or occur in a world where every event is predetermined by God.

“Just an extra note - I've been forced to consider Edwards' use of the term "Arminian" because of his context. This came about when I was working on my dissertation and I discussed the Edwards section with Iain Murray. Murray noted that the "Arminianism" faced (and detested) by Edwards was a much more Deistic, non-supernatural form of belief than what is actually held by the likes of Arminius, Wesley, etc.”

One of the reasons why I believe that Edwards is not very helpful today for contemporary discussions, is stated clearly here: his arguments were against the weakest versions of LFW imaginable. Edwards did not take on the agent causation theory/LFW of Thomas Reid, Alvin Plantinga, J. P. Moreland, Roderick Chisolm, John Searle, Timothy O’Connor, William Rowe, etc. etc. Its like Edwards pitched against minor leaguers and never actually pitched against major league competition.

Dan wrote:

“Preference is synonymous with choice. It’s not that preference causes choice, but rather preference is choice. Choice (or preference) is the act of the will, and it follows the last dictate of the understanding. So again, it’s not preference > choice, but rather understanding > choice (where preference = choice).”

If preference is synonymous with choice, then whenever we make a choice we are making a preference of one possibility rather than another. But if we are facing such a situation where we can prefer (or choose) one possibility over another possibility (or vice versa) then is it not true that in that situation we HAVE A CHOICE?

And if we have a choice in that situation, then is it also true that that choice is not predetermined (because if that selection is predetermined then we did not **have** a choice)?

And if that choice is not predetermined but could go either way, then is it not true that the claim that all events are predetermined (as Edwards believed) is false?

Robert
Godismyjudge said…
Hi Robert,

I had said:Preference is synonymous with choice. It’s not that preference causes choice, but rather preference is choice. Choice (or preference) is the act of the will, and it follows the last dictate of the understanding. So again, it’s not preference > choice, but rather understanding > choice (where preference = choice).

Hum... this probably was unclear, but I was actually trying to summarize Edwards' view, not state my own. Calvinists today try to summarize Edwards view as choosing according to our strongest desire, but that's not what Edwards said. Edwards didn't think desires (or preferences) cause choices. He thought reason, not desire, causes choices. Today's Calvinists seem to missunderstand Edwards on this point.

Edwards has to borrow the concept of having a choice from the noncalvinist, to speak about having choices because his own system eliminates the possibility of us ever having choices.

That's exactly right.

God be with you,
Dan

Popular posts from this blog

Responsibility - Evaluation of Arminian Grounds for LFW

John Owen - Death of Death in the Death of Christ

Hodge on Ephesians 1:17-19