Muller on Middle Knowledge in Arminius’ Theology
All quotes from Richard Muller’s God, Creation, and
Providence in the Thought of Jacob Arminius: Sources and Directions of
Scholastic Protestantism in the Era of Early Orthodoxy. Baker Book House, 1991.
By way of repudiating the Reformed view, Arminius would not
only adopt a concept of scientia media, he would also argue an alternative view
of concurrence…. Walaeus notes, however, that this hypothetical knowing is not
necessarily to be understood as a third kind of knowledge separate from the
scientia simplicis intelligentiae.
Arminius argues precisely the point that the definitions offered by his
Reformed contemporaries have purposely excluded. After his basic set of definitions, Arminius
presents the thesis that:
The Scholastics say besides, that one kind of God’s
knowledge is natural and necessary, another free, and a third intermediate
(mediam). (1) Natural or necessary
knowledge is that by which God understands himself and all possibilities; (2)
free knowledge is that by which he knows all other beings; (3) middle knowledge
is that by which he knows that “if this occurs, that will happen.” The first precedes every free act of the
divine will. The second follows the free
act of the divine will. This latter act
indeed is preceded by the free will, but sees any future thing as a consequence
of it… middle [knowledge] must intervene in things that depend on the freedom
of creaturely choice. (Disp. Pub.
Iv.xliii) (in Muller p.155-156)
Molina refers specifically to the statement of Origen that
“a thing will happen not because God knows it as future; but because it is
future, it is on that account known by God before it exists,” as cited by
Aquinas, and specifically disagrees with Aquinas’ interpretation. Aquinas has categorically refused to view the
future event as the cause of something in God or as standing outside of the
divine causality… Arminius nowhere cites Dreiedo, Molina, Suarez, or Origen and
nowhere notes the contemporary Roman Catholic debate over middle
knowledge. His only citation of Aquinas
stands in no direct relation to the question of scientia media, but it is hard
to rule out the influence of Molina and Suarez on his doctrine. There is even a hint of the famous Thomistic
citation of Origen and its Molinst interpretation in Arminius’ remark that “a thing does not
come to pass (non sit) because it is foreknown or foretold; but it is foreknown
or foretold because it is yet to be (future est).” (private disputation
XXVIII.xiv) It is also the case that Arminius’ motivation in arguing the
scientia media is identical with Molina’s: “the middle knowledge,” argues
Arminius, “ought to intervene [i.e., between natural and free knowledge] in
things which depend on the freedom of creaturely choice.” (private disputation XVII.xii) Thus the
scientia media must precede the act of will that grounds the scientia libera or
scientia visionis, and must know future events, not because they have been
willed but on the hypothesis of their future occurrence. God will, therefore, be able to ordain the
means of salvation on the basis of a hypothetical or consequent knowledge of
the creature’s fee choice in a context of grace. (p. 160-161)
In its detail, Arminius’ language of the divine decrees
veers away from the Suarezian view of predestination ante preavisa merita and
evidences some affinity for both the teachings of Driedro and Molina and the formulation
of Aquavia… Not only, moreover, can we assume that Arminius was aware of the
general outlines of the Roman Catholic debate over grace, free will, and
predestination, we can also infer from the catalogue of his library that he had
a detailed, first-hand knowledge of the positions of Driedo and Molina and,
probably of Suarez: he owned copies of Dreido’s De concorida liberi arbitrii et
praedstinatioinis divinae (Louvain, 1537), Molina’s Concorida liberi arbitrii
cum gratiae donis (Antwerp, 1595) and Suarez Opuscula theological. (Auction
Catalogue) (p. 163)
Thus, the divine will to save particular persons rests on
the divine knowledge of future contingent acts – scientia media. Indeed, it is only by the device of scientia
meida that Arminius can argue a genuinely universal will to save, resting on a
knowledge of possibility and also argue, subsequently, a genuinely specific
will to save believers only. (p. 164)
Whereas the Reformed insisted upon the almost paradoxical
point that an eternal and all-powerful God can in fact predetermine that some
events will occur as a result of contingent or free acts of creatures and can
therefore know such events according to his scientia libera seu visionis,
Amrinius follows Suarez in placing the divine foreknowledge or scientia meida
prior to the divine intervention, with the result that God can and does offer
inducements to his creatures on the basis of his knowledge of their disposition
towards or against certain acts. (p. 260-261)
Comments